INTRODUCTION
WHATS IS ETHICS?
Ethics
is the philosophical study of morality, a philosophical study of voluntary
human action, with the purpose of determining what types of activity are good,
right, and to be done, or bad, wrong, and not to be done, so that man may live
well[1].
It is often used interchangeably with morality, it is otherwise called moral
philosophy because it addresses questions pertaining morality; it is narrowed
down to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group or individual.
Ethics pertains to the individual character of a person or persons, while
morality points more to the relationship among persons.[2]
Ethics is a science of virtue or vice; it is a systematic study of the
fundamental principles of morality. Morality, in itself, is a set of natural
rule, which regulates human behaviours/actions in relation to one another in
society.
The
subject of ethics is voluntary human conduct; this includes all actions, and
also omissions, over which man exercise personal control, because he
understands and wills these actions in relation to the end he has in view.[3]
In
ethics, however, we are concerned with what we ought to do, what consequences
ought to be achieved, and what sort of persons we ought to become. In other
words, ethics is a normative inquiry and not a descriptive one. It seeks to
establish and prescribe norms, standards or principles for evaluating our
actual practices.[4]
Because ethics seeks to establish principles that prescribe what we ought or
ought not to do, it has similarities to other domains of human existence that
seek to guide behavior, such as religion.
Ethics is one of the major branches of
philosophy. It is concerned with the study of human actions in relation to its
rightness or wrongness. Thus, it is the scientific study of the behavioural
patterns of the human persons with great regards and reference to his or her
nature as a rational being.[5] Similar
to philosophy, ethics does not have a universally accepted definition; it has a
number of different meanings. The frequent use of the word ethics mostly refers
to a code or a set of principles by which people live. However, etymologically,
ethics derives from the Greek word ‘ethos’
which means character. Morality derives from a Latin word ‘moralis’ which means customs or
manners. Some moral philosophers has also tried to define ethics in their own
words: ethics is the branch of philosophy in which man attempts to evaluate and
decide upon particular courses on moral action or general theory of conduct according
to Richard T. Garner. A. T. Radoslav in his own position states that ethics is
the branch of philosophy that deals with the value of human life in a
systematic and scientific manner. It is concerned with the type of conduct or
character that is approved of or disapproved of in terms of right or wrong or
good or bad. W. Lillie defines ethics as a “normative science of the conduct of
human beings living in societies, a science which judges this conduct to be
right or wrong, to be good or bad, or in some similar way”.[6]
Ethics has also been defined as the “set of concepts and principles that guide
us in determining what behaviour helps or harms sentient creatures.[7]
Ethics, as a branch of
philosophy, is considered a normative science, because it is concerned
with norms of human conduct, as distinguished from the formal sciences.[8] It
focuses attention on how humans can live a moral life and studies the standards
that evaluate and determine morality in the society. Ethics involves
systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong conduct,
often addressing disputes of moral diversity.[9]
The
above definitions of ethics used concepts like ‘science’, ‘normative’, and
conduct. Clarifying the concepts, ethics as a science shows that it is
systematic. As being normative, it means that ethics is prescriptive. Conduct
refers to the voluntary actions of a person.
Moral
philosophers today usually divide ethical theories into three general subject
areas: metaethics, normative ethics, applied and descriptive ethics and these
show cases the major divisions of ethics as a philosophical discipline.
Metaethics investigates the sources of our ethical principles and what they
mean. Are they merely social inventions? Do they involve more than expressions
of our individual emotions? Normative ethics involves a more practical task,
which is to arrive at moral standards that regulate right and wrong conduct.
Should I steal to meet my financial needs? These moral questions could be
immediately answered by consulting the moral guidelines provided by normative
theories. Applied ethics involves examining specific controversial issues, such
as infanticide, abortion, animal rights, homosexuality, environmental concerns,
capital punishment, or nuclear war. By using the conceptual tools of metaethics
and normative ethics, discussions in applied ethics try to resolve these
controversial issues. [10]
Descriptive ethics is concerned with the people’s opinion on what is wrong and
what is right. The distinction Line between metaethics, normative ethics, applied
ethics and descriptive ethics are often blurry but I will
throw more light by exposing them one after the other.
THE FIELDS OR DIVISIONS OF ETHICS
The
fields of ethics refer to the different and specific divisions of ethics as a
discipline. Ethics as a branch of philosophy and as a normative discipline is
subdivided into four major divisions: normative ethics, meta-ethics, applied
ethics and descriptive ethics. These are the basic and broad divisions of
ethics.
NORMATIVE ETHICS
Normative
ethics is a division of the discourse of ethics that looks into the
consequences of human actions in arriving at ethical judgments; it is mainly
concerned with the standards or principles of right and wrong behaviour. It
attempts to explain, states and often times demands obedience to a specific
rule or principle. In order words, normative ethics is concerned with
presenting and justifying a guide to right conduct. It uses terms such as good,
bad, right, wrong etc., to express preferences, decisions and choices. The
terms are also used in grading, praising, blaming, encouraging, and critiquing.
Normative
ethics, otherwise called moral philosophy, has two subsets: the first subset is
called the theory of value otherwise called axiology. It examines the
philosophical problems of goodness or badness. The second subset of normative
ethics is called theory of obligation. This deals with philosophical problems
of right or wrong conducts. Theories under this broad division of ethics do not
describe how people behave or think, rather they prescribe how people ought to
behave and think.
Normative
ethics involves arriving at moral standards that regulate right and wrong
conduct. In a sense, it is a search for an ideal litmus test of proper behavior. [11] A
classic example of a normative principle is the Golden Rule: Do to others what
you would want others to do to you. Since I do not want anybody to copy my term
paper, then I should not copy anybody’s term paper. If I do so, it is wrong.
Using
the same reasoning as in the above, the possibility of the rightness or
wrongness of an action can be theoretically determined. As an example, The
Golden Rule is a normative theory that establishes a single principle against
which we judge all actions. Other normative theories focus on a set of
foundational principles, such as moral rights to life, happiness, and liberty.
The
basic assumption in normative ethics is, there is only one ultimate criterion to
moral conduct, whether a single rule or a set of principles. Some philosophical
ethics is broad and general, seeking to find general principles or explanations
of morality. Much, however, focuses on analysis of notions central to ethics
itself. However, philosophers do not
have a universal agreement about what precisely the criterion is. For years now,
hundreds of theories have been propounded, each claiming to be the ultimate
guide. Proponents of these theories also reject rival theories. For example,
most normative ethicists reject the Golden Rule in the above form. If I am a
masochist then, according to the Golden Rule, it is morally permissible for me
to inflict pain on other people. But inflicting pain on others is clearly wrong;
hence the Golden Rule fails as the ultimate criterion of morality[12].
Another example is the conflicting theories or views of egoism and altruism.
Egoism always argues that one should do what promotes his or her personal good,
while altruism argues that the right thing is for one to always do what will
contribute to and advance the good of the majority of the people.
In
spite of the quantity of normative theories available for consideration, many
theories involve common strategies that are classified into three: (1) virtue
theory, (2) deontological theories, and (3) consequentialist theories.
1.
Virtue
theory: Virtue theory is the view that the basis of
morality is the advancement of good character traits, or virtues. A person is
good if he has virtues and lacks vices. Typical virtues include courage,
temperance, justice, prudence, fortitude, liberality, and truthfulness.
Philosophers that uphold this theory believe that morality consists of
following precisely defined rules of conduct. Presumably, one must learn these
rules, and then make sure each of his or her actions live up to the rules.
Virtue theorists, however, give less prominence on learning rules, and instead emphasize
the importance of developing good habits of character, such as benevolence.
2.
Deontological
theory: Deontological theories base morality on specific,
foundational principles of obligation. These theories are called deontological
theories, from the Greek word ‘deon’,
which means duty, given the foundational nature of our duty or obligation. They
are also sometimes called nonconsequentialist since these principles are necessary,
regardless of the consequences that might follow from our actions.
3.
Consequentialist
theory: according to this theory, normative theories, correct moral conduct is determined solely by
a cost-benefit analysis of an action's consequences, thus Consequentialism: An action is morally right if the consequences of
that action are more favorable than unfavorable.
Consequentialist
normative principles entail that one should first tally both the good and bad
consequences of an action. Second, one should determine whether the total good
consequences outweigh the total bad consequences. If the good consequences are
greater, then the action is morally appropriate. If the bad consequences are
greater, then the action is morally inappropriate.
META-ETHICS
The
term "meta" means after or beyond, and, consequently, the notion of
metaethics involves an overview of the entire project of ethics. Meta-ethics is
non-normative and is otherwise known as analytic or critical ethics. It is
mainly concerned with the language of normative ethics. Meta-ethics engages in
a critical examination and analysis of the terms employed in the discourse of
norms. Meta-ethics therefore is the study of the origin and meaning of ethical
concepts. It treats ethical concepts and propositions and beliefs systems as
objects of philosophical inquiry.[13]
There
are issues thought to be prominent in meta-ethics: (1) metaphysical issues
concerning whether morality exists independently of humans; (2) psychological
issues concerning what motivates us to be moral; and (3) linguistic issues
concerning the meaning of key ethical terms.
·
Metaphysical
issues: The metaphysical component of metaethics involves
discovering specifically whether moral values are eternal truths that exist in
a spirit-like realm, or simply human conventions.
·
Psychological
Issues: A second concern of metaethics involves the
psychological basis of moral actions, principally, understanding what prompts
humans to be moral. A common question of “why morality?” is always being asked
by moral philosophers. Variety of answers may be given but we basically act
morally to avoid punishment, to gain praise, to attain happiness, to be
dignified, or to fit in with society.
Moral psychology looks beyond the surface of these
answers and attempts to pin-point and ascertain the internal psychological
factors that are ultimately responsible for moral motivation.
·
Linguistic
issues: To a large extent, ethics involves itself with
assessing conducts and pronouncing judgments, such as “good”, “bad”, “wrong”,
“right” etc. When such assessments are made, key terms like "good,"
"right," "ought," and "should” are used.
To ascertain a full understanding of morality,
analysis of the key moral terms must be well made. This used to be a subject of
argument during the early 20th century between British and American
moral philosopher. Nuances of these linguistic words are equally analyzed. This
is evident in many ethical publications. As a result, several aspects of moral
judgments ignored by moral philosophers have been brought to the fore.
APPLIED ETHICS
This is yet another branch of
ethics. It is a philosophical examination of controversial issues from the
moral perspective. Applied ethics is therefore distinguished commonly as that
part of ethics that gives particular and direct attention to practical issues
and controversies. This branch of ethics
consists of the analysis of specific controversial moral issues such as
abortion, animal rights, and euthanasia. The central aim of applied ethics is
to apply normative principles in the examination of controversial issues.
Applied
ethics is marked out from ethics in general by its special focus on issues of
practical concern. In the contemporary world, applied ethics has been
subdivided into the following:
·
Medical ethics
·
Administrative ethics – the application
of ethical principles to administration in the world.
·
Business ethics – the application
ethical principles to business
·
Environmental ethics
·
Sexual ethics, otherwise called
bioethics.
DESCRIPTIVE ETHICS
This is an
empirical investigation of people’s belief on morality. It is a form of an
empirical research into people’s attitude. It is concerned with the proportion
of people who believe in the wrongness or rightness of an action. It is often
referred to as a comparative ethics. It normally raises the question “what do
people think is right or wrong?” it is solely concerned with the people’s
judgment of what is right and wrong.
CONCLUSION
This work as I
introduced, is a concise exposition of ethics and its major divisions and their
concerns with regards to morality. Ethics is the principle of morality and its
divisions have their specific methods of looking at and considering issues
based on morality. I exposed the different divisions of ethics and their
concerns.
The
different definitions of ethics as a discipline uses concepts like ‘science’,
‘normative’, and conduct. These concepts are clarified in order to throw more
light to our understanding of ethics as being systematic.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
1. Jonathan
Ree and J.O Urmson (Ed). The concised encyclopedia of western philosophy, third
edition. Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abinggdon, USA. 2005.
2. Robert
Audi (Ed). The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, second edition. Cambridge
university press.1999.
3. Pantaleon
Iroegbu and Anthony Echekwube (Ed). Kpim of morality ETHICS, General, special
and professional. Heinemann Educational Books (Nigeria) Plc. 2005.
4. T.
Mautner, (ed) (2000), “Ethics” in The
Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, London: Penguin Books.
5. Ethics
(Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy). http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/e/ethics.htm
(4 of 10) [4/21/2000 8:41:53 AM]
6. W.
Lillie, (1948), an introduction to ethics, London: Mathuen
and co. ltd, pp. 1-2.
7. R
Paul, and L . Elder, (2006), the miniature guide to understanding the
foundations of ethical reasoning, united states: foundation for critical
thinking free press
8. Ethics." Microsoft® Encarta®
2009 [DVD]. Redmond, WA: Microsoft Corporation, 2008.
9. J.P
Thiroux (1986), ethics, theory and
practice, 3rd ed. New York: Macillian publishing company, p. 2
10. Singer,
P. (ed.) (1991) A Companion to Ethics, Oxford: Blackwell.
11. William
A. Wallace, op. the element of
philosophy.society of st. paul New York.1977. p49
[1]
William A. Wallace, op. the element of
philosophy.society of st. paul New York.1977. p49
[2]
J.P Thiroux (1986), ethics, theory and
practice, 3rd ed. New York: Macillian publishing company, p. 2
[3] William
A. Wallace, op. the element of
philosophy.society of st. paul New York.1977. p49
[4]
Journey to philosophy encyclopedia lawhead
[5] Pantaleon
Iroegbu and Anthony Echekwube (Ed) Kpim
of morality ethics (General, special and professional). Heinemann
Educational books (Nigeria) PLC. 2005. P.29.
[6] W.
Lillie, (1948), an introduction to ethics, London: Mathuen
and co. ltd, pp. 1-2.
[7] R
Paul, and L . Elder, (2006), the miniature guide to understanding the
foundations of ethical reasoning, united states: foundation for critical
thinking free press.
[8] "Ethics." Microsoft®
Encarta® 2009 [DVD]. Redmond, WA: Microsoft Corporation, 2008.
[9]
See “ethics” in http://www.Iep.utm.edu/ethics/
(retrieved on 4/3/14)
[10] Ethics
(Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy). http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/e/erasmus.htm
(5 of 5) [4/21/2000 8:41:41 AM
[11] Ethics
(Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy). http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/e/ethics.htm
(4 of 10) [4/21/2000 8:41:53 AM]
[12]ibid
(5 of 10)
[13]
T. Mautner, (ed) (2000), “Ethics” in The
Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy, London: Penguin Books.
No comments:
Post a Comment