MORAL DILEMMA
The
philosophical debate on moral dilemma is basically concerned with two major
issues: the question with regards to what moral dilemma is, and the question
regarding the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma. Some philosophers have
expressed their doubts with regards to the possibility of having a genuine
moral dilemma. These philosophers do not concern themselves with discrediting
the testimony of actual agents; rather they challenge the suppositions that
provide ground for a genuine moral dilemma.
All
these are based on the philosopher’s belief about the implications of accepting
the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma. They considers its (genuine moral
dilemma) problematic for the intelligibility of our moral concepts and the
coherency of our moral theories. Subscribing to the possibility of a genuine
moral dilemma may lead to a conclusion that our moral concepts are not
reasonable and incoherent.
It
is apparent that the claim of a genuine moral dilemma conflicts with some of
our foundational assumptions about morality. This is because of a situational
possibility of one being faced with two competing and mutually exclusive
courses of action, that are both morally obligatory, out of which he must at
least violate one of them, the result will show that the moral theory of the
individual is incoherent and practically useless. If this is the case, then
moral theories would apparently be giving its agents incoherent advice that is
unintelligible and inconsistent. If it is the case that following a seemingly
plausible moral theory brings predicament, then the theories would hardly be
regarded as a reliable.
The
possibility of a genuine moral dilemma triggers questions with regards to if
moral theory and morality plays the presupposed role they are believed to be
playing, could it be coherent, meaningful practical, intelligible etc. The
philosophical discussion of moral dilemma challenges us to revisit and
scrutinize our beliefs regarding the contents of our moral concepts and the
relationship among them, and reassess our beliefs about the structure and
content of moral theories. This discussion has not really concerned itself with
issues concerning agents confronted with moral dilemma. The question of what
makes an apparent moral dilemma genuine and the possibility of a genuine moral
dilemma are questions of academic interest.
Serious
moral persons are interested in the issue of moral dilemma because of the
practical and personal crisis the dilemma may cause, and equally because the
questions approach methods and responses to moral dilemma are connected
intimately with the sense of their own moral identities.
WHAT
ARE GENUINE MORAL DILEMMAS?
**Referring
to a situation as a moral dilemma in contrast with a purely practical problem
is to emphasize that the choice confronting an agent is morally significant.
People confronted with moral dilemma are cognizant of the fact that their
difficulties include matters of moral concern. Agents’ objects reflections
include matters regarding the scope and weight of obligations to promote the
well-being of those likely to be affected by their actions; a correct
interpretation of the involvements in treating others with respect and a
question of the degree of the priority given to the obligation. **Calling it a
dilemma in distinction to a perplexing possible problem, is to suggest that the
interpretation of the situation confronting an agent with two mutually
exclusive choices is correct. The agent is not incapable of making decision, or
inept in practical reasoning. Nor is the agent’s perception distorted by
unacknowledged reason-eclipsing emotions.
The
agents’ confusion with regards to what to do cannot be understood adequately as
a visible sort of epistemic limitation casting shadow over the undertakings of
situated human beings. Although no one knows the consequences but the claim of
the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma where agents are faced with
insoluble conflicts between equally compelling and competing moral
requirements, out of which he must at least violate or dissatisfy one, is not
an acknowledgement that the epistemic limitations inherent in human condition
can have a remarkable moral consequence.
To
call it a genuine moral dilemma as opposed to clear dilemma for agents in
specific circumstances is in a way suggesting that the dilemma is inevitable.
Specifically it suggests that the beginning of the dilemma does not base in
identifiable prior moral misconduct of the agent that is facing the dilemma. It
is not unusual to see people facing moral dilemma after engaging themselves
with morally problematic conducts. It is obvious that prior misconduct lays
foundation for moral dilemma. One cannot meet two competing commitments he may
have undertaken though each may be equally biding and a failure to honour any
of them is catastrophic. In this case, since the moral dilemma arose as a
result of a prior moral misconduct, it is not a genuine moral dilemma because
its emergence is avoidable.
Many
philosophers have concerned themselves with the discussion of a genuine moral
dilemma and it has been most actively disputed. The truth of the claim with
regards to a genuine moral dilemma appears to be posing a blatant threat to the
understanding of ordinary moral concepts, the coherence of moral theories, and
the practicability of morality itself. Agreeing with the possibility of a
situation where it is obligatory to do x, yet admit that to do x is not right,
it would be odd with the conditions of our use of ordinary moral concepts like
rightness, wrongness and obligation. It equally challenges understanding of the
link between rightness and wrongness with obligation, and our impressions about
the logical relationship between them. If I act based on obligations, then I am
right and I cannot be wrong at the same time. An obligation to do x and a conviction
that doing x is wrong is a contradiction, incoherent and puzzling and it need
an explanation. The claim of rightness while acting based on moral obligation,
and a voluntary choice not to do x when I believe it is an obligation, is
wrong. Both shows clearly our view of the logical relationship between the
concept of obligation, rightness and wrongness and may look like unchallengeable
truth about any adequate moral theory.
Similarly,
this applies to the presumed links between my choice not to do something
because of my belief in the wrongness of it, and my presumed non-guilt for not
doing it. Though there are complications in the possibility of subtle
differences in the conditions of blaming and agent and judging an action to be
worthy of blame, it would be clearly troubling to suppose that there would be
no special suspension of the mechanics of blame and condemnations when an agent
does x convinced that both doing x and not doing x is wrong. If it is the case
that the agent is confronted by two acts that are wrong, as it could be the
case that the agent is faced with a genuine moral dilemma, then reconsideration
is needed about our views of the logical connection between wrongfulness and
blame.
It
is suppose that one cannot be obliged to do something if he/she cannot do it.
If we cannot avoid an action, it is thought that we cannot be accused to have
acted wrongly. If this is the case, there is problem both on the practical and
theoretical aspects and more confusion about the relationship between them.
When can an agent faced with two competing options (x and not x) be said to
have acted accordance to his/her moral theory? And what critical force can be
tagged to the judgment that one acted wrongly in doing x when it is also the
case if he/she does not do x? Acknowledging the existence of a genuine moral
dilemma requires we abandon our view that “ought
implies can” and its clear consequences.
Taking
seriously the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma, we are then committed to
reject many moral concepts of our regular use, or revising them: denying the
presumed relations we hold between them. Philosophers have raised credible
questions with regards to the intelligibility of the presumptions that underlie
our assessment of moral responsibility, and the possibility of us having the
ability of making a rationally persuasive determination of practical
responsibility. Most of the factors that forms the basis of the context in
which agents act are outside the agent’s control. Some are even as a matter of
luck and are not proper objects for moral assessment. The place of luck affect
the action pattern of the agent, and indirectly our judgment of the agent’s
action, the degree of his/her responsibility for acting so, and a question as
to whether in some significant sense, an agent’s virtue or vice remains
unresolved. In such case, there is good reasoning to question our intuition
about the link between responsibility and ability, expressed in the “ought implies can” doctrine, is
defensible with a well-understood foundation. Certainly the admission of the
possibility of a genuine moral dilemma is clearly incompatible with the
doctrine that “ought implies can”
cannot be taken as foundation to deny that there are genuine moral dilemma.
Philosophers
who doubt the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma believe that the problems
posed by the possibility of moral dilemmas are deeper that those that attempt
to interpret the dictum that “ought
implies can”. They believe the possibility of a moral dilemma inflicts
havoc at essentials of moral theories. It allows the possibility of moral
theories that are quite satisfactory, comprehensive, intelligible, and
plausible for example can be incoherent, inconsistent and impracticable. If
this is the case, then acknowledging the possibility of facing genuine moral
dilemma if we yield to a particular moral theory must lead us to lose
confidence in that moral theory as a source of our precepts of action, or as a
foundation upon which our choices are justified as morally defensible. Whether
this would criticize plausible and attractive moral theories on purely
intellectual grounds, or render them irrelevant is purely an academic question.
It bereft morally serious people the sort of guidance they seek and hope to
find when they are faced with serious moral dilemma: our expected problems and
we want people to take it with seriousness.
The
argument of denying genuine moral dilemmas because of our failures is not what
we should refer to as decisive, or especially as compelling. There are other
reasons for questioning the soundness of our presuppositions about the logic
and nature of moral concepts, the role of moral theories and the fact that
genuine moral dilemmas can be encountered is not something that is fatal to
moral theories. This may provide evidence that the theories have problems, but
that is much a weaker and more contestable claim.
Though
the concern of many philosophers is the truth and falsehood of the logical and
metaphysical claims regarding the possibility of genuine moral dilemmas, we can
consider few, if there are any moral dilemmas. Defending such claim does not
require a wrestle with the complexities of the logical relations between
concepts. Strategy of retrospective
assessment might be used. This strategy involves an attempt to tender the
disinterested assessments of an agent’s opinions and their values. Discussions
on the possibility of a genuine moral dilemma are prioristic and unaffected by
the details of any agents’ moral experiences and struggles. The strategy of
retrospective assessment emphasizes the importance of sensitiveness to the subtle
differences surrounding the emergence of a genuine moral dilemma. They are in
the position to explain an agent’s belief that these circumstances constitute a
genuine moral dilemma and how and why particular agent’s impressions were
mistaken. Our recognition superior epistemic value of after-the-fact analyses
gives the strategy of retrospective assessment its plausibility. From a retrospective
vantage point, we see why an agent may have believed that there were two
exclusive options available, and why he/she must are seen the options as
equally problematic. It is recognizable that the agent in material terms is wrong;
there were more than two options, and they are not equally problematic. When
finally we embrace the strategy of retrospective assessment, reasonably we may
hope to achieve greater appreciation of the context that brought about the
agent’s dilemma arose. In many cases, it may involve us believing that a comprehensible explanation of the
beginning of the agent’s dilemma involves discovering that the agent’s prior
misconducts facilitated the emergence of the dilemma. In this case, we are
justified in saying that the agent is actually faced with dilemma which is as a
result of his fault; the dilemma is not a genuine one.
Invoking
the retrospective assessment strategy is familiar and intuitively plausible. It
also is helping us to construct a deeper explanation of the human phenomena
encompassed by moral dilemmas. We are equally reminded of the fact that humans
are prey to vulnerabilities and distortions of judgment and perception, and it
can result deep moral indecision, confusion and regret. Using retrospective
assessment, we enhance an appreciation that the human perspective is flawed and
limited. The limitations of an agents’ perspective explains why the dilemma
seems insoluble to him/her, giving us basis to deny their insolubility. Mature
agents adopt retrospective stance in assessing their deeds and confusions that
face other agents. They are able to appreciate the limitations inherent in
their stance as being finite, and acknowledge the importance of noticing that
problems that appear insoluble actually may not be so.
Invoking
retrospective assessment strategy in challenging accepted genuine moral
dilemma, we may be seen as attempting giving substance to crucial matters.
Individuals can face dilemmas that appear insoluble, and suffer great
consequences, but this does not support the claim that there is indeed genuine
moral dilemma. The inability to give solutions to what is taken as genuine
moral dilemma does not make the dilemma genuine, just as my inability to solve
a mathematical problem does not mean the problem have no solution. Appealing to
the strategy of retrospective assessment leads to the conclusion that genuine
moral dilemmas are rare than we suppose, but cannot justify that genuine moral
dilemmas are impossible. We make use of the retrospective analyses in
diagnosing perception, but this does not doubt the possibility that moral
dilemma may have been genuine. No human is perfect, but this does not mean we
cannot be classified as virtuous or vicious, right or wrong.
Appreciating
the challenges to the existence of genuine moral dilemma seems to be missing
from the discussion of moral dilemma, but it does not question the conditions
of the possibility of us criticizing people’s moral choices. The agent’s
appreciation of the need for action gives us the nature and significance of
moral dilemmas. When we confront the question: are there genuine moral
dilemmas? The question amounts to semantics: an agent’s situation can place
him/her in a serious personal moral dilemma whether it is classified as a
genuine moral dilemma or not.
APPLICATIONS
***Are
there inevitable genuine moral dilemmas? There are basis for an affirmative
answer. Focusing on agent’s deliberations and instances, there will be a lack
of genuine moral dilemmas. We are frequently faced with insoluble dilemmas. Our
speech is vague; all the moral questions do not present the agent with two
opposing options, and not all are dilemmas. There should be resistance to the
suggestions that issues like abortion, capital punishment and assisted suicide
are reductive and presents an agent with one moral dilemma. Appealing to the
experiences of mature human beings, we are inclined to conclude that there are
genuine moral dilemmas. If our concern with moral dilemmas extends beyond their
logical implications, then we should be interested in exploring specific
examples, some details maybe altered and the name of the principle changed, but
the incident is one that actually occurred.
People
in great jeopardy may have faced genuine moral dilemmas. It is a genuine moral
dilemma is not merely because it posed a difficult problem that was not clearly
soluble. It may also be called genuine moral dilemma just to show that the
agent’s decision must have been agonizingly difficult for him/her. The most
striking feature of an agent’s situation, the one in the virtue of which it
merits the description of a genuine moral dilemma, is the significance of
making a decision in such a situation. In making a decision he forges a link of
his/her moral identity. Genuine moral dilemmas present agents with situations
in which their choices are horribly constricted. Acknowledging genuine moral
dilemma is not to affirm that life is tragic or that morality fails in
situations that present us with terrible or tragic choices.
No comments:
Post a Comment