Friday, 14 October 2016

thomistic tradition: HOW TO SPEAK ABOUT GOD



INTRODUCTION
The concept of God is a subject of philosophical debate. Atheistic philosophers deny the existence of God contrary to the positions of the theistic philosophers who affirm God’s existence. The being of God transcends physicality.  However, Philosophers had tried to provide suitable way to speak of God, since being transcendental; He is beyond the qualification of our human language. However Thomas Aquinas tries to provide an answer to this question in his Summa Theologica when he talks about the metaphysics of predication and his Negative and Positive theology. The focus of this paper is how we speak of God in the context of Thomas Aquinas’ metaphysics of predication and his Negative and Positive theology.
AQUINAS ON HOW WE SPEAK ABOUT GOD
According to Aquinas, God is the super-eminent darkness which transcends human knowledge. Can we speak of God? Is it possible to qualify God with our human language? How do we use our human language in reference to God? It is undeniably true that we can speak about God. But Aquinas holds that we can never know positively what God is.[1] However we can speak of God in two ways: the negative and the Positive way. Aquinas sort to clarify the questions of, “do we use words in reference to God as we used them in reference to corporeal beings?” this lead to Aquinas’ metaphysics of predication.
AQUINAS’ METAPHYSICS OF PREDICATION
Words according to Aquinas do not have the same meaning when we use them in reference to God and man. Aquinas stipulated three predications, possible ways to use words:
·         Univocal predication
·         Analogical predication
·         Equivocal predication
These three predications differ in themselves. According to Aquinas, in univocal predication, we speak of two things in exactly the same way with the same meaning. In analogical predication we speak of two things with regards to their similarities. In equivocal predication we speak of two things in completely different ways. However, these predications come with language but Aquinas rejected univocal and equivocal language, he sees them as improper references to God. Univocal languages make God equal and same with human beings, which is not the case. Equivocal languages make God totally different from human beings, which is also not the case. Aquinas argues that if God is totally different form us, then we cannot know anything about him.
In his metaphysics of predication, Aquinas holds that the analogical predication is the most proper to apply when we speak of God. This means that we speak of God, making use of analogical language. In other words our language is similar when we speak of God and when we speak of man. But our meanings differ with regards to their degree of perfection.
Scholars are hesitant to agree with Aquinas on his teaching concerning the definition of theological language (the language we use to speak of God).[2] But it is maintained that the analogical predication, in addition to the meaning a given name is properly applied to both God and creatures, and it is specified that the reason for this predication is the fact that creatures are produced by God.[3] Hence God created corporeal beings with certain similarities with his own being.
Having asserted that we can speak of God analogically, Aquinas says that we use concrete nouns to refer to concrete things that are composite of matter and form, and we use abstract nouns to speak about God. Aquinas argues that recourse to the analogy of being is necessary, because for him, this does not only express similarity on a dynamic level between God and his creatures but also a similarity on the ontological level.
Aquinas established two criteria for this analogy: distinction between simple and mixed perfection and distinction in our words of the modus praedicandi and the res predicata.[4] For Aquinas, we arrive at a religious language from the experience of things in this world. There are simple and mixed perfection in creatures. However, only the absolute simple perfection can be directly and properly attributed to God; they are applied eminently to God rather than creature. These include things like goodness, wisdom, virtue etc. but mixed perfection is applied to God metaphorically.
In the second distinction, the res praedicata is the perfection itself, while the modus praedicandi is the mode of realization it takes in creatures or in God. Man perceives perfection through creatures, and he gathers perfection according to the mode of realization proper to creatures. In other words, we know this perfection based on their realization in us. So we cannot perceive the absolute and totally perfect mode belonging to God.
“For this reason, Aquinas concludes that if we wish to correctly use our language to refer to God, then we must preserve only the res significata and  eliminate the modus significandi. Human words never indicate the divine mode of the perfections we wish to say of God. In this perspective, our words are always enfeebled.”[5] The eminent realization of perfection in God surpasses our comprehension and expression.
AQUINAS’ NEGATIVE THEOLOGY
Aquinas’ negative theology stands in a long tradition, reaching back to Hellenistic Judaism, Middle Platonism and many patristic writers. Aquinas mitigates the starkness of the axiom about God’s absolute unknowability and proposes a domesticated version of Dionysian Negative theology and makes it compactible with the positive theology. For Aquinas, God is indeed that super-eminent darkness which transcends our knowledge and leaves us in ignorance.[6] We are ignorant of God because God's infinite reality and perfection surpass and exceed every conception of our intellect.

The ultimate human knowledge of God occurs when someone “knows that he does not know God, inasmuch as he realizes that what God is exceeds everything we understand about him.” Aquinas in his negative theology synthesizes his view of God's incomprehensibility in two theses: that no creature by its own natural powers can possess a quidditative grasp of God's essence, which “remains totally unknown,” but at best can know only that God is and what God is not; and that no creature can ever possess a comprehensive, infinite grasp of the divine essence, even in the beatific vision.[7] To have quidditive knowledge is to know essentially.
Aquinas’ negative theology has three forms:
·         Qualitative negation: this is the kind of negation Aquinas has in mind when he said although we cannot know what God is, we can know what he is not.
·         Objective modal negation: these are corrective negative judgments applied to positive divine perfections.
·         Subjective modal negations: these deny that the subjective, human way in which we understand positive divine perfections are to be attributed to those perfections themselves.
For Aquinas, our knowledge of God can grow as we add the negations one to another, and we approach closer to the divine mystery by denying more and more imperfections of God and by realizing ever more deeply that we cannot impute to God our finite and creaturely modes of being and understanding.[8]
AQUINAS’ POSITIVE THEOLOGY
In his positive theology, Aquinas continually asserts that we can make true judgments about God’s very nature and being, whether by reason or by faith. He argues that the positive nature of predications like “God is good” cannot simply be reduced to negative interpretations. Rather, he claims that such predications tell us something true about God’s very nature.
CONCLUSION
Words define ideas and ideas are applied to things. Since we can have an idea of God, we can speak of him in words, although these words do not point to the essence of God directly. We speak literally of God, but in an imperfect way, and we use words in reference to God analogically with respect to his perfection. However, our human language gives us an imperfect but complementary view of God’s perfection.
Aquinas’ theological epistemology implies that when we talk about God, the very meanings of the words we use are somehow dependent upon what we hold to be true about God. Aquinas’ God-talk blends both the positive and the negative, but the positive is foundational for the negative, for God is the pure positivity of infinite Being who in creation has also acted positively on our behalf.

REFERENCES
Joseph Omoregbe. A simplified History of Western Philosophy, volume one: Ancient and Medieval Philosophy. Lagos: Joja Educational Research and Publishers, 2007.
Battista Mondin. A History of Medieval Philosophy. Bangalore: Theological Publications, 1991.
Gregory Rocca, O.P. “Aquinas on God-Talk: Hovering Over the Abyss” in Theological Studies. India: Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology, 1993.


[1] Joseph Omoregbe, A simplified History of Western Philosophy, volume one: Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, (Lagos: Joja Educational Research and Publishers, 2007), P. 142.
[2] Battista Mondin, A History of Medieval Philosophy, (Bangalore: Theological Publications, 1991), P. 335.
[3] Ibid
[4] Ibid, p. 337
[5] Ibid, p. 338
[6] Gregory Rocca, O.P, “Aquinas on God-Talk: Hovering Over the Abyss” in Theological Studies, (:Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology, 1993), P. 4
[7] Ibid, p. 6
[8] Ibid, p. 8

No comments:

Post a Comment